Here is an excerpt from an article defining and defending what it calls after-birth abortion:
Euthanasia in infants has been proposed by philosophers3 for children with severe abnormalities whose lives can be expected to be not worth living and who are experiencing unbearable suffering.
Euthanasia in infants has been proposed by philosophers3 for children with severe abnormalities whose lives can be expected to be not worth living and who are experiencing unbearable suffering.
Also medical professionals
have recognised the need for guidelines about cases in which death seems
to be in the best interest
of the child. In The Netherlands, for
instance, the Groningen Protocol (2002) allows to actively terminate the
life of ‘infants
with a hopeless prognosis who
experience what parents and medical experts deem to be unbearable
suffering’.4
Although it is reasonable to
predict that living with a very severe condition is against the best
interest of the newborn,
it is hard to find definitive arguments
to the effect that life with certain pathologies is not worth living,
even when those
pathologies would constitute acceptable
reasons for abortion. It might be maintained that ‘even allowing for
the more optimistic
assessments of the potential of Down's
syndrome children, this potential cannot be said to be equal to that of a
normal child’.3 But, in fact, people with Down's syndrome, as well as people affected by many other severe disabilities, are often reported
to be happy.5
Nonetheless, to bring up such
children might be an unbearable burden on the family and on society as a
whole, when the state
economically provides for their care.
On these grounds, the fact that a fetus has the potential to become a
person who will
have an (at least) acceptable life is
no reason for prohibiting abortion. Therefore, we argue that, when
circumstances occur
after birth such that they would have justified abortion, what we call after-birth abortion should be permissible.
In spite of the oxymoron in
the expression, we propose to call this practice ‘after-birth abortion’,
rather than ‘infanticide’,
to emphasise that the moral status of
the individual killed is comparable with that of a fetus (on which
‘abortions’ in the
traditional sense are performed) rather
than to that of a child. Therefore, we claim that killing a newborn
could be ethically
permissible in all the circumstances
where abortion would be. Such circumstances include cases where the
newborn has the potential
to have an (at least) acceptable life,
but the well-being of the family is at risk. Accordingly, a second
terminological specification
is that we call such a practice
‘after-birth abortion’ rather than ‘euthanasia’ because the best
interest of the one who dies
is not necessarily the primary
criterion for the choice, contrary to what happens in the case of
euthanasia.
Failing to bring a new person
into existence cannot be compared with the wrong caused by procuring
the death of an existing
person. The reason is that, unlike the
case of death of an existing person, failing to bring a new person into
existence does
not prevent anyone from accomplishing
any of her future aims. However, this consideration entails a
much stronger idea than the one according to which severely handicapped
children should be euthanised. If the
death of a newborn is not wrongful to her on the grounds that she cannot
have formed
any aim that she is prevented from
accomplishing, then it should also be permissible to practise an
after-birth abortion on
a healthy newborn too, given that she
has not formed any aim yet.
-
The moral status of an infant is equivalent to that of a fetus, that is, neither can be considered a ‘person’ in a morally relevant sense.
-
It is not possible to damage a newborn by preventing her from developing the potentiality to become a person in the morally relevant sense.
We are going to justify these two points in the following two sections.
You can continue reading, if you have the stomach.
You can continue reading, if you have the stomach.
No comments:
Post a Comment